You don't need to be signed in to read BMJ Blogs, but you can register here to receive updates about other BMJ products and services via our Group site.

Philosophy, Bioethics and Otherworldliness

31 Aug, 12 | by Iain Brassington

Hmmmm.

So Brian L picked up on Catarina’s post that picked up on Brian E’s post that picked up on the ever-simmering stuff about male circumcision – and the American Academy of Pediatrics’ latest policy position in particular – with the comment “Philosophers are a bit unworldly, but this is still quite something”.  I take the implication of that to be that, even by the standards of philosophers, this debate is abstract and abstruse and perhaps even a little omphalosceptic.

The comment reminds me of a conversation that Muireann Quigley and I had with someone – I can’t remember who – a couple of IAB’s ago: this unknown person – whom I think was a medic rather than a philosopher – was wondering aloud about the number of papers on things like enhancement, and IVF, and so on, and whether there weren’t more important things for bioethicists to think about – notably what to do about the various things that actually do directly threaten the life and welfare of real people right now.

And so I got to wondering about whether philosophers can get too self-involved, hypothetical, and distracted by peripheral issues.  For example, to return to the circumcision thing: it may be that circumcising boys significantly wrongs them, but in the grand scheme of things, it’s not a great harm.  Circumcision of girls is a significant wrong, too, but the harm is greater – and so stopping that practice may strike us as more urgent just for that reason.  But it wouldn’t be completely incoherent or mostrous for someone to think that some third thing was more pressing a concern than either: if rescuing the child from the pond for some reason means missing out on the opportunity to lobby against genital mutilation, then you should rescue the drowning person all the same.

Quite how we prioritise things might be a matter for debate – and there’s an important higher-order question about how you rank harms and wrongs, and how you could compare significantly harmful situations with significantly wrongful ones, given that neither implies the other.  Still, the idea that A might be more morally important than B, which is more important than C or D or E isn’t crazy; and the idea that male circumcision (for the sake of argument, a significant wrong but much less significant harm) is quite a long way down the alphabet doesn’t seem unreasonable either.  So there’s some sense in the idea that it’s a bit strange to devote a huge amount of attention to it.

But this presents us with the first defence of otherworldliness – or, at least, what might seem like otherworldliness.  Given that there’s any number of calls on our moral attention, we need some way to figure out which are the most pressing, and whether all of them are pressing in any way at all.  Working that out might be a whole lot easier, and the answers easier to illustrate, by means of thought-experiments that are not directly related to particularly pressing real-world needs.

Second, in the process of doing that, we might well find that there are all manner of interesting real-world problems that present themselves that we wouldn’t otherwise have noticed.  Some of them – like circumcision, for example, might not be hugely pressing: but, on the other hand, they might strike us as being low-hanging fruit.  Third, being slightly unworldly allows bioethicists to do horizon-scanning work, and so ought to make it easier to respond to pressing needs when they do arise.  Famously, a lot of policymakers and bioethicists were caught on the hop when Dolly the sheep was cloned, and there was a lot of legal and moral catching up to be done, some of which was quite poor; but bioethics as a discipline is now – at least in that field – much better prepared to deal with the kinds of new technologies that could start to appear over the coming couple of decades (I think.  But then again, there might be something else that noone foresaw…).  A lot of ground on genetic ethics, ectogenesis, and so on has been secured that arguably wouldn’t have been if bioethicists had paid their full attention on what is currently a pressing need.

Fourth – and I think that this is quite important – philosophy as a whole is quite otherworldly (in the sense of being impractical, and in the sense of being vorhanden), but a similar charge can be pressed against any number of other disciplines.  Do x-ray crystallographers or cosmologists or anthropologists do much directly to relieve current significant harms and right current significant wrongs?  Unlikely.  Does that mean that their time could be better spent?  In one sense, perhaps – more lives will be saved and the common weal advanced by providing a latrine in every village, and they could be helping on that front.  Does that mean that people oughtn’t to be x-ray crystallographers or cosmologists or anthropologists?  Not a bit of it.  Some things are worth doing because their benefits are indirect; but sometimes, they’re worth doing for their own sake.  Whether they’re more worth doing for their own sake than some other thing is a matter for debate – but it’s a debate that takes us straight back to the ranking problem.  So I think that there is often a defence to the charge of otherworldliness – it can be of indirect benefit – and sometimes there doesn’t have to be a defence.

Thoughts, anyone?  If there’re no comments, I’ll assume that I’m wrong, and everyone’s out digging a latrine.  Well done.

By submitting your comment you agree to adhere to these terms and conditions
  • http://twitter.com/BioethicsUK Nathan Emmerich

    I saw that comment by Brian L. yesterday and I too wondered what it was he meant! Tracing the comments by *B*rian (presumably L) and not *b*rian (presumably E) on New Apps today seems to indicate he meant equating female and male circumcision could only be the product of an ‘otherworldly’ mind. He doesn’t seem to think that ‘in the real world’ they are morally comparable acts. I would be inclined to agree. One severely impares sexual functioning, the other does not.

    However, you raise a set of interesting points. Of course Bioethics was (is?) an attempt to be somewhat *less* otherworldly although may of the methods of philosophical applied ethics are, precisely, otherworldly. Counterfactual reasoning etc all makes appeals to ‘other’ worlds!

    To stick with Brian E (et al), something along these lines has troubled me about the recent ‘love drugs’ stuff (and nootropics more generally). Bioethical analysis is often predicated on quite specific, but nevertheless speculative, claims. Why would a love drug save a marriage and not, for example, render you emotional siblings? Such ‘horizon scanning’ will, of necessity, be science fiction but I do wonder if this is where the sexy bioethics is at rather than where the difficult and troubling actual moral and ethical issues of the day are to be found.

    Of course, one response might be that the difficult and troubling moral and ethical issues of the day receive little illumination when analysed in the otherworldly frame of philosophical applied ethics – it will require other sorts of bioethicists to really get to grips with them.

    To stick with the love drug example. If it actually became a reality that couples could take drugs to ‘enhance’ their relationship. In effect, to prevent their relationship from disintegrating. What would the ethical and moral issues be? I think they would, at least in part, centre around social expectation that would arise for couples, particularly those with children, to take such drugs and to stay together. There may also be some problem with couples who take such drugs and whose relationship nevertheless fails. Is this discussed in the speculative bioethical literature on love drugs? Not as far as I have seen. Such things are dismissed under the idea of couple autonomously choosing to take such drugs whereas, for me at least, it is where the real issues are to be found.

  • http://www.facebook.com/richard.scalper Richard Scalper

    hey, great b*!!$^!t logic to postpone outrage over what’s cruel & sick on girls, no problem on boys. ~Dick-Scalper

  • http://www.law.manchester.ac.uk/aboutus/staff/iain_brassington Iain Brassington

    Is there all that much literature on love drugs out there? I’ve not looked particularly hard – but, from what I’ve seen, most of the work seems to come from a fairly small group that we already know to be quite technophile… but I’ll say no more, because I like this job.
    *ahem*
    On the subject of what’s troubling – well, I suppose that there’s always going to be a worry about deciding just how troubling something is, and how we rank it (on which, see Kelly’s post here: http://www.kellyhills.com/blog/yet-another-person-me-wibbling-about-kuhn-paradigm-shifts-bioethics/ ).
    But I’m really not sure I agree with your claim that things that we agree to be troubling may receive little illumination when considered by philosophical bioethics: why would anyone think that? What’s the evidence and where’s the argument?

You can follow any responses to this entry through the RSS 2.0 feed.

Latest from JME

Latest from JME

Blogs linking here

Blogs linking here